In my previous post I
set out a view of the relationship between the interaction order and social
structure. I want now to discuss the forms of integration or malintegration
that exist at each level. These issues were famously discussed by David
Lockwood in an article of 1964 through his distinction between ‘social
integration’ and ‘system integration’ (in Explorations in Social Change,
edited by Zollschan and Hirsch). My claim is that social integration should be
seen as relating to the interaction order and system integration as relating to
the macro-level social structure.
A state of social
integration exists when interacting individuals and groups establish shared
understandings that permit a coordination of their actions. They produce a
negotiated order that underpins their joint action. Where there are failures in
mutual understanding and a resulting lack of coordination, there is social
disorder, rather than social order, and the potential for social
disintegration. This was discussed further in David Lockwood’s Solidarity
and Schism (1992). The larger social structure that emerges as a
virtual reality from this interaction order comprise a relational and
institutional structure with a particular degree of ‘system integration’. This
state of system integration is an emergent property of the virtual structure
and it is important to explore the specific connections between this and the
state of social integration.
The elements
comprising a relational structure are what Lockwood described as the
‘non-normative’ factors, comprising a ‘substratum’ of ‘the factual distribution
of means’ that set limits on the opportunities available to actors and imply
specific interests for them. The connections among these elements are what
Pitirim Sorokin referred to as ‘causal-functional’ integration. The ‘parts are
related to one another, directly, or, if indirectly, by several internal
“centers”’ (in an extract from his 1937 book in System Change, and
Conflict, edited by Demerath and Peterson). These connections are internal
to the relational structure itself.
They are systemically
interdependent because the change or elimination of one part ‘perceptibly
influences the rest of the synthesis’ and a part when found in a different
combination of parts cannot exist or undergoes profound modification to become
a part of the combination. Sorokin added that ‘the degree of functional unity
or functional interdependence is everywhere not the same’. That is to say, the
degree of integration is variable.
This point was taken
up by Alvin Gouldner in his contribution to the same volume. He argued that
only in certain cases does the system interdependence of parts comprise a
stable and enduring ‘equilibrium’. The degree of ‘functional reciprocity’
between parts can vary, departures from full reciprocity resulting in varying
degrees of instability. Disequilibrium occurs when interdependence is low, as
the parts have considerable ‘functional autonomy’. The greater the extent to
which a part tends to maintain its autonomy, the greater is the ‘tension’
within the structure as a whole. Disequilibrium also occurs when
interdependence is high but involves negative feedback. Ion this situation the
parts operate in ways that undermine each other. Lockwood followed Marxian
terminology and referred to this situation as involving structural
‘contradictions’ between the relational parts. His example is Marx’s claimed
contradiction between the forces and relations of production within the
economic structure of a capitalist mode of production.
The elements
comprising an institutional structure are what Lockwood referred to as the
normative elements. Whereas a relational structure is a system of ‘energy’
pressures resulting from the limits imposed by the structural constraints, an
institutional structure is a system of ‘information’ connections in which the
degree of ‘fit’ between elements is a matter of their meaningful coherence. The
information connections comprise what Sorokin called ‘logico-meaningful’
integration and coherent clusters of these normative elements comprise social
institutions. The state of system integration characterising an institution or
structure of institutions and norms can be described, Sorokin argued, using
terms such as consistency, complementarity, or logical contradiction (as
against the material contradictions of the relational structure). Thus, an
element may be internally inconsistent or contradictory and may be
inconsistently combined with other elements.
Margaret Archer
shared much with Sorokin’s point of view, but emphasised the relevance of
Popper’s view of the (Hegelian) world of ‘objective knowledge’. Viewed as a
cultural system, she argued, an institutional structure is a ‘corpus of intelligibilia’
(Culture and Agency, p. 104) that stand in a logical relationship to
each other and so may be judged as consistent or contradictory. As an
objective, emergent property of the institutional structure, the state of
system integration can constrain the actions of individuals. For example, the
norms of a language (which may be inconsistent or even contradictory) constrain
speakers and so shape what can be said and how it is understood.
There is, of course,
a definite relationship between the institutional structure and the relational
structure, though this is not a simple one-to-one relationship. There social
structure is a complex combination of institutional and relational structures and
it is necessary to look at the integration of relational structures, the
integration of institutional structures, and the integration between these two.
Talcott Parsons famously analysed the state of perfect integration—fully
institutionalised social relations—where the one-to-one relationship is clear.
This, he argued, allowed the sociologists to study the simplest form, of social
structure as a preliminary to understanding its more usual and more complex
forms of low integration. As Karl Mannheim recognised the social world is not
‘a single and completed structure, but an aggregation of partially structured
orbits’ (‘Towards a sociology of mind’, p. 75). The recognition of varying
degrees of system integration is a way of placing this at the centre of attention.
Similarly, there is
no one-to-one relationship between social integration and system integration.
David Lockwood’s paper highlighted this as a fundamental limitation of the
Parsonian view, which assumed that one could be read off from the other. It is
important to analyse separately the integration at each of these levels and
then to trace out the mechanisms that link the two together and that are
responsible for the variations and disjunctions between them. In short, the
ways in which intentional actions have unintended and unanticipated
consequences, which establish new conditions that constrain future actions.
Originally Posted August 7 2017
Comments
Post a Comment