In Objectivity
and Subjectivity in Social Research, which I wrote with Gayle Letherby and
Malcolm Williams (Sage Publications, 2013), we set out an account of
objectivity and truth in relation to the necesarilly subjective basis of social
knowledge. This posting outlines a summary of the key arguments of the book.
Why are so many
sociologists concerned with objectivity and the pursuit of ‘truth’ when our
knowledge and understanding of the social world is so self-evidently subjective
and partial? The conventional view in all the sciences has been that it is only
by securing objective knowledge that we can be guaranteed that it is true and
that we can therefore avoid the claims of our critics that we are biased in our
viewpoint and are merely parading ideology in the guise of science. This is an
important justification of the search for objectivity, but many critics,
especially in the social sciences, have argued that it is unrealistic:
objectivity is seen as impossible and truth as unattainable. All knowledge, so
the criticism goes, is relative to the particular point of view that we take on
the world, and our point of view is rooted in our values. As these values
differ from one individual or social group to another, so our knowledge must be
regarded as a value-bound cultural construction: there are no ‘facts’ and so
there can be no truth.
A recognition of the
subjectivity of human knowledge does not, however, mean that we must reject
objectivity and truth. Whilst we may, indeed, need to abandon any idea of
‘absolute’ or ‘ultimate’ truth, it is nevertheless possible to acquire
knowledge that is true to the objects of our knowledge but also true to the
standpoints from which we observe those objects. Social science can attain a
partial truth that has no objective validity but that is also authentically
true to its various observers. Social science rests on a balance of objectivity
and subjectivity, each equally indispensable to the other.
The starting point is
that of Immanuel Kant, who drew a sharp distinction between the subjectivity of
observed ‘phenomena’ that are contained within the minds of human observers and
the unobservable ‘noumena’ that make up the world of objects that exist
independently of the mind of the observer. There is, he argued, an unbridgeable
gulf between the world as it is perceived in human experience and the world as
it actually is. A noumenal reality is a condition for any human experience, but
the phenomena that we experience are mere subjective constructions of this
reality. Human observers, therefore, can never grasp the true nature of the
things that they observe.
Kant based his
argument on two assumptions about human beings and the human mind. First, he
held that what we are able to perceive is dependent on the nature of our
perceptual and sensory apparatus. For example, we see objects as we do because
our visual apparatus is constructed in such a way as to produce a
three-dimensional, colour image in our mind. Animals with differently
constructed eyes and visual receptors do, literally, see the world differently:
they see a different world, perhaps a two-dimensional, monochrome world.
Similar considerations apply to our senses of touch, smell, and hearing, and so
there is no way in which we can claim to know the world as it ‘really’ is. That
world remains unknown, independent of our senses.
Kant’s second point,
however, is that the mind does not passively receive sense impressions. There
are innate cognitive ideas of time, space, causation, etc that underpin the
organisation of our perceptions and allow us to relate them to general concepts
(dog, man, tree, earth, etc) that are pure products of the mind. The conceptual
knowledge produced by science, therefore, is doubly relative to the human mind
and cannot be judged in terms of its ‘correspondence’ with reality. Human experience
is a mental construction and we must abandon, it would seem, any idea of
objective truth.
Max Weber and
Heinrich Rickert took a similar view and applied it to the historical and
social sciences. In doing so, they added an important element to Kant’s position.
They argued, first, that in addition to relating sense impressions to innate
categories and concepts, the social scientist relates his or her impressions of
the social world to values. We necessarily take a value stance towards the
social world and so our concepts must be seen as value-relevant, as relative to
our values. To this argument they added a further point: that the real social
world that exists independently of the social scientist is itself a product of
the value-relevant activities of its human participants. We all, in our
everyday lives, construct impressions of the others that we encounter and
interact with, and these impressions are relative to our sensory apparatus,
mental ideas, and cultural values. Thus, the social scientists is engaged in a
second-order activity of ‘understanding’ the social world that Weber aimed to
grasp through his idea of Verstehen. Where the natural scientist
can describe and explain the natural world, the social scientist must interpret
and understand it.
Weber, however, did
not draw extreme relativist conclusions from this. He argued that, whatever our
value position, we are able to follow technical procedures that can guarantee
objectivity. We can be clear and precise in our conceptualisation, rigorous in our
handling of data, logical in our deductions and inferences, and scrupulous in
giving attention to alternative interpretations. That is, objectivity for Weber
lies in the methods through which we handle our experiences rather than in our
experiences themselves. Objectivity is a purely technical matter that can
guarantee the truth of an argument relative to a particular value starting
point. Anyone holding the same values who followed the same technical
procedures would come to the same conclusion. Thus, there can be a plurality of
truths, reflecting a plurality of values, but it is possible to reject some
inferences and explanations as false because the methodology used is faulty.
While this might seem
to resolve the question of objectivity and to reconcile it with the necessary
subjectivity of human experience, some writers have regarded it as overstating
its case by ignoring the possibility that the technical criteria themselves may
reflect a particular value choice. The roots of this more radical argument are
to be found in the work of Friedrich Nietzsche, who had also been a major
influence on Weber himself.
Nietzsche argued that
values must be seen as embedded in historically specific social circumstances
and embodied in persons with specific bodily characteristics. He claimed that
all knowledge is, therefore, perspective-bound. We see and interpret the world
from our particular historical and bodily standpoint of power relations. Those
who are located differently will see the world differently. All knowledge is
situated knowledge and gives a view of the world from a particular location.
For this reason, there is no ‘view from nowhere’ and so there is no
objectivity. The idea of truth, for Nietzsche, is a mystification: instead of
absolute truth we have, at best, a tentative and partial consensus among those
in similar locations. Knowledge is linked to power and what counts as truth is
merely the knowledge of the powerful.
One of the earliest
positions to express the view that was set out by Nietzsche is to be found in
Marxist theories of the dependence of knowledge and consciousness on the class
standpoint of the observer. Marx saw class relations, rooted in property and
the lack of property, as generating interests that motivate action and
constitute the standpoint from which class members construct their views of the
world. Class relations define a horizon of possibility that limits the ability
of people to see the world in particular ways, and the ideas of the dominant
class come to form a dominant ideology. If the subordinate class, instead of
viewing the world from its own standpoint and interests can be made to accept
this dominant ideology—perhaps through its imposition by schools and the mass
media—their ideas can be characterised as a ‘false consciousness’. Falsely
conscious workers have come to take the standpoint of the bourgeoisie and so do
not see their own position clearly. Criteria of truth and falsity are,
therefore, relative to class locations. Georgy Lukács, a Marxist associate of
Max Weber, held that there can, therefore, be both a ‘bourgeois’ science and a
‘proletarian’ science. The technical criterion of objectivity on which Weber
had placed his hopes on are, according to Lukács, simply bourgeois criteria and
provide no basis for achieving truth. The truth of particular forms of
consciousness is established only through the practical actions pursued in
class struggle. Truth, then, is a product of history.
More recently, a
related position has been taken within feminist theory by those who argue that
the gendering of social relations constitutes distinctive gendered standpoints
on knowledge. Following, in particular, Nietzsche’s emphasis on embodiment,
they argue that the particular social position of women, largely confined to
domesticity and excluded from many spheres of public activity, provides a
distinctive standpoint from which their experiences of the social world are
constructed. This is opposed to the standpoint that men take in the
construction of knowledge and the power balance between men and women is such
that ‘malestream’ views become the dominant form of knowledge and, by virtue of
male power, can be imposed as the taken-for-granted ruling ideas.
Similar views have
been developed in postcolonial theories, which posit an opposition between the
social standpoints of the coloniser and the colonised, and in theories of
ethnic division and the racialisation of knowledge. Most radically, writers
such as Kimberlé Crenshaw have pulled these positions together in theories of
‘intersectionality’, using this term to refer to the ways in which class,
gender, ethnicity, sexuality, and other social divisions cross-cut in complex
systems of oppression and domination. Instead of simple dichotomies of
standpoint and knowledge there is a myriad of social locations and a
fragmentation of knowledge.
This radical
relativism might seem to imply that the whole idea of truth must be abandoned.
Perhaps we can no longer claim to judge accounts as true or false but simply as
‘different’. This is the position taken by many postmodern writers, who hold
that as all knowledge is socially constructed, there is no reality: there is
merely a variety of constructed realities that form a ‘hyperreality’. From this
point of view, the social sciences are simply one set of intellectual games
among many others and there can be no way of choosing between sociology,
poetry, science fiction, and commonsense knowledge except on the basis of
purely personal and arbitrary preferences.
A way forward was
suggested by Weber’s contemporary Karl Mannheim in his sociology of knowledge.
Mannheim recognised the relatedness of knowledge to social position but held
that this need not lead to relativism. He argued that we must not privilege any
one standpoint but must recognise that all standpoints generate subjectively
valued truth: each perspective provides an authentic and so valid construction
of reality. Combining these authentic but partial truths into a single account
gives a more comprehensive—but not absolute—truth. This is the position that
Mannheim called ‘relationism’.
Relationism holds
that all socially situated knowledge that is an authentic expression of
particular concerns and interests can be regarded as relationally true.
Relational truths are partial and limited but are essential elements in a
comprehensive synthesised account of the world. Such a synthesis, embodying a
variety of truths in a single view, is not the truth, but it
has a truth that goes beyond the partial truths that it incorporates.
Mannheim’s position
can be understood by thinking of the different views of a room that are taken
by those located at different points within it. Each person sees the room from
a particular position and so sees it in a particular way. A synthesis of these
differing viewpoints gives a more comprehensive, more accurate picture of the
room as it really is. Of course, the social world is vastly more complex than a
room, but the logic of Mannheim’s argument is the same. A combination of
partial but authentic viewpoints of the social world can produce a composite
truth, an account with a greater truth value than any of the positions taken
separately.
But who is to
construct this composite synthesis? As there can be no ‘view from nowhere’,
would the synthesis not be an equally partial truth bound to the particular
social standpoint of its producers? Mannheim’s answer is both ‘yes’ and ‘no’.
The synthesis can be produced, he argued, by a social group that is ‘relatively
unattached’ from any particular standpoint. This social group is the intellectuals
who are drawn from various social classes, genders, and so on, and whose
position within the university gives them a relative freedom from social
determination and allows them to take a wider and more comprehensive point of
view.
This might appear to
be self-serving: Mannheim was, after all, an intellectual. His argument was,
however, that there the social conditions of intellectual life must be such
that there are certain institutional guarantees that intellectuals will
consider all partial truths equally and will maintain their relative detachment
and impartiality. These institutional guarantees comprise the values of
academic freedom and free, rational discussion in open and unconstrained
situations protected by the organisation of the university. These conditions
describe what Habermas would later describe as the ‘ideal speech community’, a
sphere of discourse free of constraint and power relations in which all can
engage on the basis of equality—regardless of class, gender, ethnicity, or
other social division—and can consider arguments solely in terns of their
intellectual merit.
Mannheim was aware,
of course, that such conditions are precarious. He and his teaching assistants
ion the Department of Sociology at Frankfurt University had been forced to
abandon their posts and leave the country when the Nazi government had imposed
tight political controls over the universities that removed all vestiges of
academic freedom and excluded particular value positions and ethnic groups from
participation in intellectual discussion. He argued, therefore, that there was
a need for constant vigilance to protect and maximise academic freedom.
Universities must create the conditions in which academics from all social
backgrounds have equal opportunities to participate in intellectual discussion
and must ensure a relative detachment from commercial and political pressures
that would limit this discussion. Only when such conditions exist can the
pursuit of objectivity be guaranteed. Where those conditions do not exist we
are left with the possibility that certain partial truths will be excluded and
that falsehoods may be perpetuated.
The objective pursuit
of truth, through the synthesis of partial subjective truths, is the task of
social scientists acting under conditions of academic freedom and free
discussion.
Of course, an account with truth value must conform to its object
in some way. So, if ‘correspondence’ with reality is rejected, in what does
this conformity consist? Mannheim’s argument was that conformity with reality
is demonstrated by the ‘practical adequacy’ of knowledge. Indeed, testing for
practical adequacy is a principal way in which partial truths are distinguished
from falsehoods and the various political truths are balanced against each
other and synthesised. Thinking originates in attempts to solve practical
problems and a truthful view of the object world is one that provides effective
ways of addressing those problems. If a theory ‘works’, it has practical truth
value. True knowledge is that which provides us with expectations and leads us
to actions that are effective in the practical contexts that are of interest to
us. Such knowledge grasps some aspects of the noumenal reality that is, in its
totality, unknown and unknowable. This partial approximation to the truth is
all that we can hope to achieve: it is what it means for a subjective observer
to be objective.
Originally Posted November 16 2017.
Comments
Post a Comment