Skip to main content

Structures, Subjectivity, and Virtual Reality

In an earlier posting I discussed the idea of the ‘social mind’ and the way in which such a collective consciousness’ must be understood as dispersed to and contained in the minds of the individual members of a society. This provides us with a way of understanding social structures, seen by Durkheim as external and constraining factors in social life. In my work on social structure I showed that the institutions and relations that comprise a social structure must be seen as ‘embodied structures’, but I did not properly specify how such individual phenomena relate to collective structures.
In this posting I want to try to show that the structures of everyday life—Goffman’s ‘interaction order’—and the ‘macro’ structures of specialised economic and political activities can be understood as rooted in individual subjectivity yet act as real forces in shaping individual activity.

The world of everyday life—the backdrop to all our activity—comprises the myriad locales and persons that are typically encountered—houses, shops, roads, pavements, workplaces, etc.—and all the various objects that they typically contain. The everyday world is a sedimentation of our experiences, the sedimented elements that can be taken-for-granted as what ‘everybody knows’.

The everyday world becomes broader and deeper as more aspects of specialised activities become routinised and sedimented. Places newly encountered may be assimilated by us to our understanding of the everyday world as they become more familiar to us. In contemporary societies, the department stores where we do our shopping have become parts of the everyday world. As we become more familiar with staying at hotels, aspects of hotel life, too, come to be familiar and are sedimented in the everyday.

Aspects of our school or work life may become extensions of our everyday world: those parts that we regularly encounter on a day-to-day basis and that are familiar to us. Similarly, a person elected to parliament will come to see aspects of the Palace of Westminster and its surrounding public buildings as everyday phenomena, though they remain unfamiliar, and often closed, to others.

The specialised activities in which we engage—going to work, lobbying parliament, attending church, etc.—all take place against the backdrop of the everyday world, yet all add to this a distinct point of view and view of the world that acts as a frame of reference to shape our specialised actions. Thus, the everyday world coexists with a number of distinct (and perhaps mutually discrepant or contradictory) realities. Each specialised activity depends upon a commonality and complementarity of understanding: there must be some common understandings that define the nature of the activity and some complementarity of understandings that ensure the actions of those in different social positions will mesh. This complementarity may not form a perfect concordance between actors. All that is necessary is that there be sufficient congruence for their interaction to be mutually predictable.

The everyday world and the specialised worlds may be largely intersubjective realities, by virtue of being similarly understood by all members of a society. Each individual may understand the world differently—uniquely—but there will be a greater or lesser commonality or overlap in views. Whenever such a commonality exists, individuals will tend to act in such a way that their interactions mesh: the relations in which they engage are expressions of the common understanding and the definitions of situations that they inform.

When there is sufficient commonality in subjective orientations, whether in everyday or specialised activities, it is as if the actors are acting under an external structure that shapes their actions. Speech, for example, is experienced as if it were governed by an externally real linguistic structure, in terms of which utterances may be judged to be grammatically correct or incorrect. However, in speech and in interaction generally there are no separate structures but merely virtual structures: structures that are experienced as real but that exist only in the subjectivity of individuals and the communicative flows that sustain them. It is the commonality and complementarity that ‘contains’ the virtual structures that can be said to be governing their actions.

Social structures are, therefore, virtual structures. They can be identified and their properties be described by sociologists, but they have no substantive existence apart from the individuals whose subjectivity sustains them. The virtual structures that we can identify (concepts, values, norms, roles, institutions, etc.) may be more or less integrated or contradictory depending on the degree of coordination that is achieved between the multiple realities in which actors must engage over the course of their lives.


Originally Posted June 3, 2017

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Integration and Social Structure

In my previous post I set out a view of the relationship between the interaction order and social structure. I want now to discuss the forms of integration or malintegration that exist at each level. These issues were famously discussed by David Lockwood in an article of 1964 through his distinction between ‘social integration’ and ‘system integration’ (in  Explorations in Social Change , edited by Zollschan and Hirsch). My claim is that social integration should be seen as relating to the interaction order and system integration as relating to the macro-level social structure. A state of social integration exists when interacting individuals and groups establish shared understandings that permit a coordination of their actions. They produce a negotiated order that underpins their joint action. Where there are failures in mutual understanding and a resulting lack of coordination, there is social disorder, rather than social order, and the potential for social disintegration. This...

Objectivity and Subjectivity

In  Objectivity and Subjectivity in Social Research , which I wrote with Gayle Letherby and Malcolm Williams (Sage Publications, 2013), we set out an account of objectivity and truth in relation to the necesarilly subjective basis of social knowledge. This posting outlines a summary of the key arguments of the book. Why are so many sociologists concerned with objectivity and the pursuit of ‘truth’ when our knowledge and understanding of the social world is so self-evidently subjective and partial? The conventional view in all the sciences has been that it is only by securing objective knowledge that we can be guaranteed that it is true and that we can therefore avoid the claims of our critics that we are biased in our viewpoint and are merely parading ideology in the guise of science. This is an important justification of the search for objectivity, but many critics, especially in the social sciences, have argued that it is unrealistic: objectivity is seen as impossible and tru...

Interaction and Social Structure

Some of the most powerful approaches in sociology are those that analyse the interactions of individuals. These are often seen as in opposition to more abstract views of social structure. I want to argue that this is not the case and that the two approaches are complementary and imply each other. I will develop this argument in this post and will take the argument further in a later post. Interaction is the result of ongoing mutual constructions of the situation and of the attitudes and actions of its participants. Each participant constructs a representation and account and so negotiates a shared understanding that is sufficient to justify their actions as appropriate and so to ensure that the actions of the participants mesh or coordinate. Participants mutually—simultaneously and interdependently, but always imperfectly—legitimate their own actions and shape the actions of others by attempting to define limits to the options open to them. Each participant holds to an understanding...